Hello, dear friend, you can consult us at any time if you have any questions, add WeChat: daixieit

PHIL 0610

Philosophy and Science

Handout #8

Objectivity, Value Judgment and Theory Choice

I. Recap of Kuhn

Last time we saw Kuhn’s theory about the nature of scientific activity. He thinks that science goes through a series of revolutions interspersed with periods of normal science” where the paradigm within which scientists are working is taken for granted and not subject to testing.

II. Challenges to Kuhn

Kuhn’s theory about scientific revolutions has been criticized for leaving rationality out of the picture. Philosophers have made the following claims about Kuhn’s theory:

•   Kuhn thinks paradigm choice is a matter of mob psychology.

•   Kuhn thinks that paradigm choice cannot be based on good reasons of any kind.

•   Kuhn thinks that debates about paradigm choice amongst scientists involves mere persuasive displays without deliberative substance.

Kuhn was shocked by these claims. But there are some pretty good reasons that these were the conclusions his readers came to about his theory.

III. Some details of Kuhns view

Here are some of the details of Kuhns view that led others to make the above claims about it.

1.   Progress in science

When there is a shift from one paradigm to another, Kuhn cannot say that science has progressed. Why? Kuhn doesn’t think that one paradigm is better than another. The new paradigm is just different. The reason we can’t say that one paradigm is better than another, according to Kuhn, is because the means by which we might evaluate the new and the old paradigms is itselfparadigm dependent. He didn’t think that there was some neutral perspective from which to judge between paradigms. This leads us to the next claim.

2.   Incommensurability

Kuhn thought that paradigms are incommensurable. Two things are incommensurable if there is no common        standard of measurement to compare them. That is, Kuhn thought while people might argue in favor of one        paradigm or another, they would be doing so from within aparadigm. If it were possible to see this argument from outside any paradigm (from above) it would be clear that those engaged in argument are actually talking past each other. There are two kinds of incommensurability that are relevant here: incommensurability of meaning or          incommensurability of standards.

a.   Incommensurability of meaning

People debating paradigms may not be able to fully understand each other because the meanings of their words are slightly different. People operating within two different paradigms might seem to use the same word, but the meanings of these words might differ slightly. This version is less plausible than the other  kind. We would expect to see some evidence of this in the history of science.

b.   Incommensurability of standards

Kuhn argued that paradigms have their own standards for what counts as good evidence or a good argument and that these standards change across scientific revolutions.

3.   Theory-ladenness of observation

We might hope that the methods of science (e.g., observation) might permit us to get an unbiased attitude from which to adjudicate between two paradigms. But Kuhn argues that observation is not a neutral source of information for choosing between theories, science what people see is influenced by their paradigm. This is known  as the theory-ladenness ofobservation. The theory-ladenness of observation refers to the claim that observation cannot function as an unbiased way of testing theories (or paradigms) because observation is affected by the theoretical beliefs of the observer.

IV. Relativism

Kuhn’s claim that paradigms are incommensurable is largely responsible for others viewing his theory as a form of  relativism. Relativism is a complex topic. For our purposes, we will use the following definition. A view is relativist if it holds that the truth or justification of a claim depends on one’s situation or point of view. You can be a global    relativist, which would be the view that all truth (or justification) is relative. Or you can hold a relativist view about a more restricted domain such as art or morality.

Many people have interpreted Kuhn’s view about science as relativistic about standards governing reason, evidence and justification of beliefs. Kuhn himself denied that his view was relativistic in a serious way. Some claims in his   writing (e.g., incommensurability) seems relativistic, but other claims seem to dispute this. It may be that his views  can’t be fit together into a coherent whole.

V. Kuhn and theory Choice

Theory choice is a problem in the philosophy of science. The problem is to understand how scientists should choose between competing theories.

Remember that Popper had trouble finding a way to allow for rational decisions about theories. Kuhn has a similar problem, but he isn’t worried by it quite like Popper.

Kuhn claims that there are characteristics of a good scientific theory and that these criteria are shared amongst scientists.

The characteristics of a good scientific theory:

1.   Accuracy: the results that are deducible from a theory should be in agreement with the results of existing experiments and observations.

2.    Consistency: a theory should be consistent both internally but also with currently accepted theories.

3.   Broad-scope: a theory’s consequences should extend far beyond the particular observations it was initially designed to explain.

4.   Simplicity: a theory should bring order to phenomena that in its absence would be individually isolated and, as a set, confused.

5.   Fruitful: a theory should disclose new phenomena or previously unnoted relationships.

Kuhn claims that these values are shared amongst scientists, and therefore constitute a kind of objectivity. However, Kuhn argues that these criteria on their own can’t determine scientific choice. First, there will not always be agreement about whether a theory satisfies these criteria or to what extent. Second, there will be disagreement about how relatively important each feature of a theory is.

Kuhn thinks that choices between theories, despite shared ideas about the characteristics of a good scientific theory, will depend, in part at least, on idiosyncratic factors dependent on the biography and personality of the chooser. However, Kuhn doesn’t think that this makes theory choice irrational or illegitimate.

VI. Contexts of discovery and justification

Kuhn thinks that some philosophers of science might concede that he is correct that though subjective features might play a significant role in the discovery or invention of new theories, but will still maintain that objectivity enters into the picture in the process through which theories are tested, justified and judged.

The idea is that there is a significant difference between the context in which a theory is discovered or invented and the context in which a theory is tested, judged and justified.

Kuhn thinks that this idea is wrong. He thinks that philosophers have been misled by science textbooks into thinking that the process by which a theory is endorsed involves looking at straightforward experiments that seem to confirm it. Instead, Kuhn thinks that such experiments only represent a small portion of the considerations that were taken into account in choosing one theory rather than another.

Furthermore, Kuhn argues that the famous crucial experiments that philosophers of science like to point to--which seem to confirm a theory--most often occur after the theory has already been generally accepted. The results of the experiment are, by that stage, not surprising to anyone.

Kuhns two main points about theory choice are:

1.   Choices  scientists  make  between  competing  theories  depend  not  only  on  shared  criteria,  but  also  on idiosyncratic factors dependent on individual biography and personality.

2.   The shared values of what makes a good scientific theory and the discussions about theory choice that result is an essential part of science.

Kuhn’s imagined critic sees the lack of a deterministic system of theory choice as a weakness, but Kuhn regards it as a strength. Theory choice, according to Kuhn’s picture, allows for rational individuals to disagree and to discuss which theory is most suitable.

VII. Subjectivity and objectivity

We haven’t really specified what the terms subjective” and objective” mean here. This is something we will come back to in our next module. But Kuhn does have something to say about these terms too.

Kuhn thinks that there are two different senses of “ subjective” and that confusing these senses can lead to misunderstandings about his view of theory choice.

He thinks “ subjective” can be applied to matters of taste, and Kuhn thinks that his critics has interpreted him as using it in this sense. Instead, Kuhn intends subjective” in the sense of a judgment.

Kuhn asks us to imagine the following example. Suppose you see a movie with a friend. As you leave the cinema, you exclaim How I liked that terrible potboiler!”

•   Your internal state is not discussable. i.e., How you feel about a movie isn’t something that someone can reasonably disagree with you about.

•   Your judgment is discussable. i.e., Your judgment that the movie is a potboiler is something you and a friend can reasonably argue about. You can share reasons for why you judge one way rather than another.

Kuhn thinks that in the context of theory choice, we make judgments or evaluations of theories as in the second case. These are things scientists can fruitfully discuss and argue about.

‘I am suggesting, of course, that the criteria of choice with which I began function not as rules, which determine choice, but as values, which influence it. Two men deeply committed to the same values may nevertheless, in particular situations, make different choices as, in fact, they do. But that difference in outcome ought not to suggest that the values scientists share are less than critically important either to their decisions or to the development of the enterprise in which they participate. Values like accuracy, consistency and scope may prove ambiguous in application, both individually and collectively; they may, that is, be an insufficient basis for a shared algorithm of choice. But they do specify a great deal: what each scientist must consider in reaching a decision, what he may or may not consider relevant, and what he can be legitimately be required to report as the basis for the choice he has made.’ (p.362)